Prime and Maximal Ideals
4 min read
Consider the natural numbers and order them by divisibility: whenever divides . For example if I give you the set of numbers Then the "largest" number in terms of divisibility is .
This ordering may seem strange; did we just reverse the "usual" ordering on natural numbers? Not quite. While for any at least one of or is true, if we consider the numbers and under divisibility ordering we see that neither nor . This difference is why we call divisibility a partial ordering (not every pair of elements are comparable) while the usual order is a total ordering.
Maximal elements, that is elements where for any comparable we have , become much more interesting in this new ordering. In fact, if we exclude from the natural numbers, we get:
Proposition: Under divisibility ordering, the maximal elements of are prime.
Proof: Since means that divides , a non-maximal is not prime. Conversely, if is maximal then there doesn't exist any such that . In other words, has no divisors hence is prime.
Generalizing to Rings
The above divisibility relation is kind of strange: under divisibility ordering means that , but this menas that is a multiple of so under the "usual" ordering !
The reason why we reversed the ordering is because this relationship is because in the context of subrings ordered by inclusion, the maximal elements are prime.
To make the generalization, for consider the set consisting of multiples of It's obvious this is a subset of the ring , and it's not hard to see that in fact this is an ideal.
If , then for some and hence so we have the containment . Letting denote partial ordering under inclusion, we get that .
The motivation section's result can now be stated in its full generality:
Theorem: Let be a commutative ring with identity, and let be a maximal proper ideal. Then is prime.
Proof: Suppose , and . Towards contradiction, suppose neither nor . Then by maximality of , So for some . Consider the product Since is an ideal, all the summands are hence we have . But if an ideal contains , then , contradicting that is a proper ideal.
Another application of the proof technique
The skeleton for the proof technique we used above goes something like:
- Assume towards contradiction that is not prime, and let be a witness
- Use maximality of to argue that elements not originally in (and whose product should not be either) are in and
- Since we assumed , multiply the elements together
- Show that this product is in , yielding a contradiction
It turns out, mixing maximality and primality in can get us pretty far. Here's an important result from algebraic geometry:
Theorem: The intersection of all prime ideals of a ring is the set of the nilpotent elements of . That is:
Proof: If is nilpotent, then because every ideal contains . But since is prime, means that either (done) or (induct).
In the other direction, suppose is not nilpotent so all of its powers are non-zero. Consider the set of ideals of which don't contain any power of Clearly , so is non-empty. We'd like to select a maximal element of ordered by inclusion, but the problem is that there could be infinitely many ideals which satisfy this.
To make this maneuver sound, we will appeal to Zorn's Lemma. Partially ordering by inclusion, let be an ascending chain in . Consider . It's not hard to show that is an ideal (exercise: prove this, since unions of ideals are not always ideals you will need the fact that this is an ascending chain). Moreover, as a union of sets not containing powers of , contains no power of . Hence, is an upper bound for this chain. This checks the conditions for Zorn's lemma, so we may conclude there exists a maximal .
Now we apply the skeleton from before to prove is prime. Suppose otherwise, and let but and . By maximality, neither nor are in , so both must contain powers of i.e. Multiplying Since is an ideal, the right-hand side is in . But this means that , contradicting the fact that means that it doesn't contain any powers of !
Hence, is a prime ideal containing no powers of .